D&D 5E The Multiverse is back....

Aldarc

Legend
So, for me, when someone gets to the point of telling me to go read academic journals to continue a casual message-board debate, I take it as a simple admission that the counterpoint cannot possibly be understood simply by a person with no prior specialization, and so the "functional" part comes into play. A moral code only accessible to obscure specialists and deadened with jargon isn't of much functional use (at the very least, you get the tl;dr reactions folks in the thread are articulating). So it doesn't actually help people in general to answer moral questions. Which means that people trying to answer moral questions in the Real World still must struggle with functional subjectivity. Which is the kind of mindset that PS is made to evoke. And so that mindset is not unthinkably alien, even to those who believe in some objectively real morality.
I'm not sure how that rationale holds up. It's about like saying that creationism must be true on the basis that an evolutionary biologist instructed you to read scientific journals after repeated attempts to get you to understand the basic concepts of the science and to assure you that they are not just making stuff up. Your sense of the term "functional," therefore, comes across as a copout and an admission of ignorance. The accumulation of jargon increases exponentially for all fields as you advance in education and experience. And by Jupiter, it's hard to turn that jargon switch off, especially if you're in the academic mode.

tl;dr: it's fun to let players come up with their own moral codes, and that's part of the fun PS brings to D&D.
tl;dr How then is PS adding anything new to what was always the case for D&D? :erm:
 

log in or register to remove this ad

Sadras

Legend
I'm curious, what would have been the practical difference between including Greyhawk deities and making general domain deities?

It is more of a personal preference for me than determining what the practical difference is. In the 2e PHB (page 34) they presented Priests of Specific Mythoi without naming one deity but reflected spheres with possible granted powers for such spheres. In the welcome section (page 8) they refer and encourage the use of setting books, even naming FR and Greyhawk, Kara-Tur etc and that is generally where it stops.
In 3e PHB (page 106) they presented the deities not as an option, but as "these are the deities of D&D". In 4e they did the same thing, but granted this was an entirely new take on D&D (from the mythos to the mechanics), IMO.

Or are you suggesting presenting the deities as just a name and the domain associated with them and no other description?

I would suggest reflecting the domains/spheres and associated powers with no mention of deity names - I understand this is my personal preference. World setting has generally been viewed as part of the DM's workload, and that is why it is found within the DMG. Deities form part of the world setting and creation process - so if there are any possible deity names to be mentioned for the various D&D settings they would need to be included in the DMG with a reference to their specific setting books should one require more info.
In the MM under setting monsters such as the Death Knight I expect to see an info coloured block referencing Lord Soth of Krynn. This I view as setting-light.

Personally I think 5e did a good job by offering a multitude of deities and pantheons, though they still retained descriptive text and their associations...

Honestly, I haven't purchased the books as yet, waiting for the DMG to be released before purchasing them in one go, so I cannot provide an appropriate comment either way. But I imagine 5e's approach would have to be all inclusive given their primary objective.
I have no issue with descriptive text/blocks.

As a final note, I found the 2e The Complete Book of Elves was excellent in its approach when trying to cover something specific as Elven Mythos/History for the various settings, but yet remain viable for homebrewed worlds. I imagine @Hussar would be accepting of a similar style book of the Planes.
 
Last edited:

Hussar

Legend
[MENTION=6688277]Sadras[/MENTION] - yes, this is exactly what I've been banging the drum for. The Complete books for 2e were great that way. A massive bucketload of flavour, but, very setting light. Like you said, the 2e PHB listed spheres and archetypes for gods - a harvest god would likely have these spheres, a war god those spheres. I find that a much more useful sort of thing than listing specific gods from D&D settings, particularly for me, since I don't read those settings. I wouldn't have known Bane from a hole in the ground. No idea. I know very little about Forgotten Realms, so, the list in the 5e Basic book is just a bunch of words as far as I'm concerned. I have no idea who Ohgma is, other than he was the god of the priests in Candlekeep in the Baldur's Gate game.

Like I said, I don't read D&D books. They are there to be played, AFAIC. I need some flavour in order to do that - what is a Thoul, what does it look like, what does it eat? That sort of thing. But, beyond that? Get out of my way and let me play the game.
 

pemerton

Legend
has Rawls somehow overcome this "Is / Ought" divide? (Sorry if you've already addressed this, but the thread is just too long to trawl. Would you mind throwing off a sentence or so summary?)
I don't think that Theory of Justice claims to overcome the is/ought divide - the key premises for Rawls's arguments in favour of his conception of justice are themselves normative premises, namely, claims about the dictates of rationality, plus certain moral intuitions that he takes to be widely shared.

I think that, by the time of Law of Peoples, Rawls does think that the is/ought divide can be overcome in a certain fashion, namely, that certain historical truths can have normative force because of their constitute significance for our present-day forms of political life. The key truth he is interested in is the role of toleration in bringing an end to the wars of religion, which underpins what he calls "the fact of reasonable pluralism".

I don't think he is denying Hume's claim in taking this view - rather, I think he is positing that a fact can also, in certain circumstances, carry normative force for anyone who is interested in social life being viable. And he thinks that, given that human beings have no choice but to live socially, any rational person does have an interest in social life being viable.

An interesting feature of Law of Peoples is that most of the commentators on it are cosmopolitan liberals who attack Rawls for having "sold out" his liberalism, because he acknowledges that those for whom the wars of religion don't occupy the same place in history (eg Iran, perhaps Turkey, definitely IS) don't have the same reason as those who participate in the liberal-democratic inheritance to take reasonable pluralism seriously. In a certain sense, Rawls regards their non-liberalism as a type of faultless disagreement, rather than an error of reasoning.
 
Last edited:

Umbran

Mod Squad
Staff member
Supporter

Folks - per the board rules, we have to ask you to leave the current events/politics points behind. Sorry if that hamstrings your ability to discuss philosophy, but do remember that this is a board and thread about pretending to be an elf, not about real-world issues.
 

pemerton

Legend
So, for me, when someone gets to the point of telling me to go read academic journals to continue a casual message-board debate, I take it as a simple admission that the counterpoint cannot possibly be understood simply by a person with no prior specialization
Hey, Alzrius was the one asking for citations!

But here are some points that I think can be understood without prior specialisation:

* There is a scholarly discipline, moral philosophy, widely studied in English-language colleges and universities, which deals with the controversy over the nature of morality;

* Among the practitioners of that discipline, the mainstream (but not universal) view is that morality is objective;

* The reason for that view is that it best accords with features of usage - eg truth and falsehood predication, denial, contradiction etc in moral contexts don't seem to behave any differently from ordinary contexts (contrast pronouns - I can't deny your claim "I'm hungry" by saying "I'm not hungry" - I have to say "You're not hungry!" - but there is no corresponding rule for moral utterance);

* Those who think that morality is objective recognise that the methodology for ascertaining moral truth isn't going to be identical to the methodology for working out (say) how far the earth is from the sun - and they have theories of what that methodology is (eg reason; intuition; human nature; etc);

* One of the biggest issues that anti-objectivists (subjectivists/relativists) have to deal with is what I have called the "hypocrisy problem" - namely, if moral judgement is not answerable to some objective standard, then it is hard to explain how acting against someone else on the basis of one's moral judgement is any different from bullying

* There are various ways of trying to deal with the "hypocrisy problem" (eg Russell argues that compossibility vs non-compossibility of desire is key to identifying desirable courses of action without hypocritically privileging one's own moral judgement; Nietzsche embraces the implication of hypocrisy, and moves the focus of evaluation from morality to aesthetics and self-cultivation).​

I think there are also some secondary points, about the nature of argument, that can be taken away:

* "Burden of proof" is a greatly overrated technique in most serious arguments - most people are defending some view or other, and can reasonably be called upon to provide reasons for that view;

* The idea that "you can't/don't have to prove a negative" is also greatly overrated - for instance, when the Buddha denies that there is such a thing as the self, he certainly feels the need to provide an argument (given that the claim is quite contrary to common sense), and there are plenty of instances where proving a negative is fairly straightforward (eg proving that there is no greatest natural number);

* The idea that "argument from authority" is a fallacy is also greatly overrated - for instance, if I want to know what the typical views are in a discipline with which I'm unfamiliar, the best way to find out is to ask someone familiar with that discipline; and more generally, most things that I know - about physics, about history, about other places - I didn't discover for myself but learned from reading someone else's account ie by relying on authority.​


Just teasing this out (because it seems to describe the counterpoint): you could dispute this claim in a lot of ways.
  • The idea that a personally flourishing life is a moral good is not objectively true. It hinges on culturally-bound values (for instance, the primacy of the individual and the value of individual education). For instance, one could easily conceive of a conflicting definition of moral good that was family-focused (as the biological understanding of altruism may lead you to), and thus moral good would be measured based on how that child can contribute to the improvement of the family. Making carpets for people in exchange for food and board certainly could contribute to the economic well-being of the family (by taking away an expense, namely, the upkeep of the child), and thus would be a higher moral good than attending school, however miserable that child is.
  • The definition of "flourishing" is subjective. It seems to hinge on personal experience, and therefore cannot be determined from the outside. If the child, for instance, might be quite happy and content as a bonded laborer in a carpet factory until its untimely death, and it might be miserable and incapable and unhappy at school, which would make the bonded labor "objectively more flourishing" than the education. Furthermore, it cannot be known which situation will happen before the experience occurs, so it's impossible to ascribe an "ought" to any of the individual courses of action.
  • A moral code that identifies the "typical case" as determining the "ought" will be actually incorrect whenever the case is not typical, and thus not produce moral good at all. Furthermore, it presumes knowledge of what a "typical case" is or could be, which is unknowable without perfect knowledge of every human's inner thoughts (to determine what "flourishing" is). For instance, what populations are sampled and how often to determine what a "typical case" is?
  • A moral code that rests on "facts about human nature" is a castle built on sand, biologically speaking, as "human nature" itself is not only intensely individual at the genetic level, but also in constant flux both genetically and evolutionarily. Such a moral code would have to, for instance, dub milk products as a moral evil after childhood (given that they are poison to something like 70% of humanity at this point, it would certainly not lead to flourishing in the typical case). If there were some historical accident that changed "human nature," (a massive asteroid falls into Asia and wipes out most of humanity that is lactose intolerant) the moral code would have to be promptly reversed.
Sure. Those arguments can, and have, been made. And there are replies available, too. (For instance, most people who study child labour recognise the important economic contribution that it makes to family wellbeing, but they regard this as a problem - that no way of making such a contribution is available that doesn't also stunt the child's wellbeing - rather than as a marker of flourishing.)

Raymond Geuss has a nice passage in which he argues that equality is not, in general, an objective good, but that some other things might be (Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton University Press 2008) p 80):

[T]he distribution of medical services in a modern hospital can be described, depending on the frame of reference chosen, as ‘equal’ (all are to get, notionally, as much as they need), or ‘unequal’ (those seriously ill get more treatment than those with minor ailments) … There is nothing special about equality; what is objectionable is depriving people of needed medical treatment, if it is in principle available. That in most societies is a definite social ill … [T]here are any number of different reasons for thinking that mass death for want of medical help is a bad thing – it is virtually a paradigm of what we mean by a social ill – and we think in this case the reason so many people are dying is that those who need it are not receiving medical help​

There are some people, of course, who think that widespread death due to a want of medical care that is in principle available is a matter of indifference. But there are also some people who think the world is flat.

The number of people who will defend bonded child labour as something other than a social ill is, I think, comparably modest. To the best of my knowledge, there is no serious campaign under way to repeal child labour laws and Factory Acts in those jurisdictions that enjoy the benefits of them.

In itself, none of this is an argument for objectivity. But I think it shows that claims about what is or isn't a social ill, or what does or doesn't contribute to human flourishing, isn't hopeless.

and so the "functional" part comes into play. A moral code only accessible to obscure specialists and deadened with jargon isn't of much functional use
I think that you are conflating two different points here.

No one (either in this thread, or in moral philosophy) is confidently asserting that they have easy objective answers to difficult moral questions. The point, rather, is that there is some such answer or other available, and hence that our moral reasoning and judgements is answerable to, and aims at fidelity to, that answer - even if it is hard to find.

A comparison in counting would be this: no one knows how many carp were swimming around in the imperial fish pond in the Forbidden City exactly 1000 years ago from the moment I am typing this, but we all know that there was some such number, that it was zero or greater, that (if non-zero) it was either odd or even, etc. The fact that I conjecture that it was odd, and that you conjecture that it was even, and that neither of us has a good basis for rebutting the other's conjecture, doesn't mean that the issue is subjective and has no objective answer.

Likewise in morality: the main point of insisting that morality is objective is to make the point that error is possible, that belief is not equivalent to truth, and hence (for instance) that there is, at least in principle, a difference between enforcing moral requirements and the mere exercise of power. This is where I find that Planescape falls down - it abandons objectivity without seriously engaging with the hypocrisy problem, and without (in any obvious way) providing the resources for dealing with it in one or other of the ways it might be dealt with.

it's fun to let players come up with their own moral codes, and that's part of the fun PS brings to D&D.
Sure. That's why many of us don't use GM-adjudicated and enforced alignment.

But this is also why the objective/subjective issue matters - if you deny that morality is objective, then you are arguably robbing the notion of moral code of its meaning - you may as well say that each player brings his/her own taste in ice cream to the game. It is highly plausible that if moral conflict and disagreement to carry weight, it must actually be conflict, in the sort of fashion that [MENTION=49239]BenK[/MENTION] described upthread.

EDIT: [MENTION=177]Umbran[/MENTION], I've cross-posted with your mod warning. I don't think what I've said in this post is in violation, but am happy to delete/be mod-edited if I'm wrong about that.
 

Alzrius

The EN World kitten
pemerton said:
Alzrius, I don't know what you're trying to prove, but you don't seem to have understood my posts very clearly.

I understood your posts just fine; I just don't think that they're very cogent. Though you don't seem to have understood my objections to your vague references to other works that you claim support your positions, without actually citing how they do.

pemerton said:
First, you complain about a lack of citations. I have offered multiple works. Do you want page numbers for A Theory of Justice? Look up "reflective equilibrium" in the index. Do you want to read Raz's account of the interest theory of rights? From memory, it's in chapter 8 of The Morality of Freedom. These are actual examples of actual moral argumentation by leading contemporary figures who regard morality as objective.

Do you want to read a defence of non-objective morality? Then read Blackburn's Spreading the Word and Ruling Passions. Do you want to read a devastating critique of Blackburn? Then read Bob Hale's essay "‘The Compleat Projectivist’, The Philosophical Quarterly 36 (1986): 65–84. (This doesn't deal with Ruling Passions, which is a more recent work, but Hale's objections are easily extended to cover Blackburn's later work - if you PM me I can send you my relevant unpublished work.)

If you want to read the most sophisticated version of moral anti-objectivism out there, I recommend a paper I've already cited upthread: Stephen Barker, "Is Value Content a Component of Conventional Implicature?", Analysis 60 (2000): 268–79.

You don't seem to understand the nature of citing supporting evidence, which is rather odd for someone who claims to be so deeply involved in this field. If you want to state how a particular work backs you up, you have to actually quote the relevant passage, and then cite where that quotation appears. You seem to finally start doing that here in terms of citations - now if you'll actually reproduce the passages in question, then you'll finally have entered them as evidence insofar as the debate we're having.

pemerton said:
You seem strangely obsessed with quotes, as if pages of argument can be boiled down to a bumper sticker. For reasons of copyright, among others, I can't cut and paste 12 pages from Analysis, 20 from The Philosophical Quarterly and 300+ from Harvard or Oxford University Press. But do you really think I'm lying about the contents of these works? From my point of view, you're in the same situation as someone who, when told that they can learn about natural selection in Darwin's Origin of Species or Dawkins's The Blind Watchmakr asks for a quote to prove the point!

If you call "asking you to produce the works you keep referencing" to be "strangely obsessed," then you must meet a lot of obsessed people in your line of work! That said, you're now shying away from actually quoting the works you cite, which undercuts your reasons for citing them in the first place. It's not a question of honesty - that's simply a matter of common sense (and common courtesy) insofar as holding a debate goes. If you can't quote the works you're referencing, regardless of the reasons why, then you're not in a position to reference them to begin with. In other words, you mentioned them, so you need to do more than just drop a name. Why that's apparently so offensive to you remains a mystery.

pemerton said:
Moving from citations to some of the assertions that you make: You might regard your refutation as "deft". I can tell you that it probably wouldn't pass in an undergraduate essay.

A mild ad hominem attack here, which is not the hallmark of someone who actually thinks that they have a strong position. You tend to do this a lot, I've noticed.

pemerton said:
You are getting hung up on matters of "burden of proof" that have no relevance to the discussion.

They are, in fact, highly relevant; more on this below.

pemerton said:
For instance, you claim that you don't have to prove anything because you are simply denying a positive assertion, namely, that morality is objective. Well, I can play that game too, if I want: I can deny that morality is subjective, thereby - by your logic - putting the burden on you to prove that it is subjective!

Leaving aside that you think the most basic of the principles of debate is a "game," this is such an elementary proposition that I'm rather surprised you brought it out at all. How does one prove that morality is subjective? Simple. Person A says that "I think X is good." Person B says "I think that X is bad." We note the lack of any objective moral criteria to say which is more correct than the other - and any such criteria you enter would fall victim to the same principle of "it's a positive statement that morality is objective, which can be critiqued and found to be lacking" - and ergo, we find that morality is subjective.

In other words, the subjective nature of morality is plainly self-evident. Trying to say that there's an objectively true element to morality, by contrast, places a much larger burden of proof on you because there is no such self-evidence in play; the first person who disagrees with you on any moral matter puts that proposition to rest!

pemerton said:
There are some arguments where burden of proof matters, but this is not one of them. You are advancing a theory of the semantics of moral discourse and the metaphysics of morals. Your theory is as affirmative as that of any objectivist. If you want anyone to take it seriously, you have to provide reasons for it.

This is incredibly backward. This is indeed an argument where the burden of proof matters - if you say that there's an objectively true morality, then it's incumbent on you to demonstrate that. You're proposing an objectivist notion of morality, and then being critical of the idea that that same level of objectivist thinking can be used to poke holes in the idea. It's hard to take that seriously if you posit that such a line of thought affirms your stance, but can't be used to critique it.

pemerton said:
That's what Blackburn, Gibbard, and their predecessors such as Russell, Ayer, and Hume do. Even the existentialists, who are less interested in technical argumentation than analytic philosophers, give reasons for thinking that there are no objective criteria for value. (I mean, Being and Nothingness is notorious for its length. What do you think Sartre is doing in all those pages, if he doesn't feel the need to show that his anti-objectivist conception of value is correct?)

Again, quote the relevant sections or stop appealing to other works. Demonstrate the points you feel that they're making, rather than alluding to them.

pemerton said:
Moving onto your actual claim to have refuted me: you don't even seem to know what you're refuting. You seem to think you are providing reasons why morality is not objective - though I haven't actually noticed any (eg you haven't pointed to any facts of usage, any metaphysical considerations, etc - I think you are gesturing at an argument to best explanation, but you are not engaging with any of the relevant data points that such an argument would have to deal with).

At this point, it's simply enough to note that you have yet to demonstrate your claim that morality could be considered objective under any particular circumstances. Since making such a claim is incumbent on your demonstration of evidence to that effect, and no such evidence has been put forward yet (which can stand up to scrutiny, at least), then your position has yet to advance. Hence why I've pointed out that your stance has been refuted.

pemerton said:
But in any event, I have not asserted that morality is objective. Nor have I denied that it is. As I stated a long way upthread, I am not interested in having that argument on this board (and, as I have also stated, I am happy to circulate my relevant work by PM if you are interested).

This is a semantic distinction, as you have made attempts to demonstrate the manner in which an objective morality could supposedly be determined.

pemerton said:
All I have done is to point out that (i) the mainstream view among analytic moral philosophers is that morality is objective, (ii) there are certain reasons for that view, draw mostly from considerations of usage of the sort I have pointed to, (iii) objectivist moral philosophies aren't just hand waving, but rather have theories of epistemic acces to moral truth, and of methodology in moral reasoning, and (iv) relativist/subjectivist views face a non-trivial challenge that I have labelled the hypocrisy objection.

Likewise, all I've done is (i) express some degree of skepticism to that effect, since you're claiming to speak for a majority without showing why that'd be the case (beyond "it's in some books/journals. Really.") (ii) I don't doubt that there are reasons, but rather I question the cogency of that line of reasoning, (iii) I'm not saying that objectivist moral philosophies are "hand-waving" per se, but rather are dependent on them meeting the high bar of showing how one demonstrates an objective moral truth - the very fact that their theories are questionable is a major strike against them, as the whole point of something objective is that it maintains its existence even if disbelieved. Since moral truths don't sustain that level of existence, those theories are therefore insufficient in terms of the advancing the point that they're arguing, and (iv) the hypocrisy objection does not survive scrutiny, because the recognition of moral relativism does not necessitate that having a personal moral doctrine, while still recognizing the subjectivity of such doctrines, be hypocritical when it clashes with another doctrine that holds different moral views.

pemerton said:
You haven't given any reason to doubt (i) - for instance, you haven't identified any mainstream analytic moral philosophers who are anti-objectivist. I believe that's because you don't know of any. For instance, my guess is that you've never read Simon Blackburn or Allan Gibbard or Terrence Horgan or Mark Timmons, and so don't recognise them as leading moral anti-objectivists. (And, for that reason, as opponents of the mainstream view.)

I would also point out that, contrary to what you say in your post, the question of whether a certain view is mainstream among a group of academics is an objective matter of fact, whether the academics are philosophers or geologists.

Saying "my opinion is the norm" is not a question of doubt - as I've mentioned many times before, if you want to say that something is the way it is, you're the one who needs to demonstrate that. You're purporting that you speak for a majority of people in a given field; that's a major claim to make, and saying that it's self-evident does not live up to the standard that you seem to think it does. You drop a name or two, and are under the impression that that somehow satisfies the burden of evidence that you've taken upon yourself. This is rather odd, considering that you even seem to then admit that the point of view you claim to represent is not so obvious as the consensus regarding physical facts.

pemerton said:
You have not seriously enaged with (ii). For instance, you haven't addressed the difference between falsehood predication in the context of first-person pronouns (which are subjective in meaning) and in the context of moral argument. And your claim that it is "outlandish" to claim that "and" is a truth-conditional operator - a view which has been mainstream at least since Frege - suggests that you've not taken an introductory course in either logic or philosophy of language.

The last sentence is more ad hominem nonsense - if your argument hinges on "oh really, you know less than X," then it's already a weak argument. It's notable that once you remove that, you really have no counter-claim in this entire paragraph, other than the fact that you must use the conjunctive "and" in one particular way and only that way. If your point can't survive having the assumptions that it rests on questioned, then your point can't survive at all.

pemerton said:
You have not engaged at all with (iii). For instance, you haven't given any reason to think that moral truths can't be derived from facts about human nature (for instance, what is your argument against the claim that going to school rather than working as a bonded labourer in a carpet factory does not, in the typical case, give a child an objectively more flourishing life?).

Once again, it's up to you to showcase that moral truths could possibly be derived from facts about human nature, which you haven't done. The very fact that the example you posit has to use the clause "in a typical case" showcases the invalidity of that argument - if something were objectively held to be true, it would not be "typical" but absolute. Since your phrasing inherently denies that level of certainty, it therefore can't be held to derive a fact regarding an objective moral truism.

pemerton said:

With regards to (iv), the mod warning is such that I'm not going to post a reply here, which is a shame.

pemerton said:
Nietzsche, and some who follow him, are prepared to deny these distinctions, but they recognise that this is radical revisionism. I'm not sure you've really given the issues the same depth of thought.

I recognize your uncertainty, and would like to reassure you that you're incorrect here.

BenK said:
Alzurius - I'm trying to make sense of the paragraph starting 'It's actually a powerfully developed argument', but I'm having trouble making headway. If A says of B 'What they are doing is wrong' and B say 'We are not doing wrong' I can see two possibilities:

1. The A's claim that B's actions have the property of being wrong is correct, and therefore B's claim that their actions do not have the property of being wrong is incorrect;

2. B's claim that their actions do not have the property of being wrong is correct, and therefore the A's claim that their actions do have the property of being wrong is incorrect.

This is a false dichotomy - since there is no objective metric by which one can measure the property of correct or incorrect in each case, the initial premise in each of those two outcomes ("have the property of being wrong") cannot be reached, which undercuts the findings that are then concluded. Hence the subjective nature of what constitutes the properties or morally right and wrong.

BenK said:
In the case of the second possibility obtaining - B's actions having no property of being wrong - it could be that some actions do have the property of being wrong, and B's actions do not happen to have that property, or it could be that no such property exists at all (in which case all claims that any action 'is wrong' are simply false.)

I'd amend that last point to say that "simply false" is operating under the presumption that there must be something objectively true or false. The subjective nature of an idea - which is what morality is - is such that one person can hold a proposition to be moral, and another person can hold that same proposition to be immoral, and they can both believe themselves to be right and the other wrong, with no inherent contradiction therein.

BenK said:
Obviously, perceptions of right and wrong - as are all perceptions by definition - are subjective. But if someone claims that something _is_ right or wrong, the claim is either true or it isn't. If 'right' and 'wrong' aren't properties that actually exist, then claiming some action or state of affairs have those properties is simply an error, no?

Claiming something has an objective state, when no such objective state can be conclusively shown to exist to begin with, would be a statement of belief that's purporting to be a statement of fact. The very action of claiming that something is right or wrong is a perception unto itself.
 

Remathilis

Legend
I'm fairly confident that both bronze dragons and holy avengers have seen far, far more use in play than the hand and eye of Vecna.

Btw Rem, from the bottom of my heart, thank you for the brevity and concise nature of you comments. :)

Well granted, its not like the Eye of Vecna is on the random treasure table (though it might!) so its not like DM's hand it out haphazardly; they usually have a plot necessity to do so. A better example is putting stats for the Tarrasque in the Monster Manual; how many times are you seriously going to fight him?

And no problem; I've been skipping past the alignment/moral debate too.
 

pemerton

Legend
[MENTION=8461]Alzrius[/MENTION]:

I assume that you accept that there is such an academic discipline as analytic moral philosophy.

I assume that you also accept that the practitioners of this discipline - moral philosophers - have opinions about, and debate about, the semantics of moral utterance and the metaphysics of morals.

From those two premises, it follows that one of the three alternatives is true:

1) The mainstream view among these philosophers is that morality is objective;

2) The mainstream view among these philosophers is that morality is subjective;

3) There is no view that is mainstream among these philosophers.​

Now, with resepct to these three alternatives, there are three epistemic possibilities:

A) The true alternative is known;

B) The true alternative is not known but is knowable;

C) The true alternative is not known, because unknowable.​

I assert (A) that the true alternative is knowable, and is known, and also (1) that the mainstream view among these philosphers is objective.

I assume that you are not asserting (C) - it would be odd to say that this particular fact of human opinion was unkowable.

Are you asserting (B)? On what basis - an inference from the fact that it's not know to you to the conclusion that it's not known to anyone? Are you asserting (2)? On what basis?

In general, the opinion of a member of a group is good evidence of what that group thinks. I don't really understand on what basis you reject my testimony as to the mainstream view of members of my discipline. (You also seem to be assuming, with no evidence, that I share that mainstream view.)

Also, as for this argument:"Person A says that "I think X is good." Person B says "I think that X is bad." We note the lack of any objective moral criteria to say which is more correct than the other - and any such criteria you enter would fall victim to the same principle of "it's a positive statement that morality is objective, which can be critiqued and found to be lacking" - and ergo, we find that morality is subjective."

Here is a parallel argument: "Person A thinks that the number of fleas on Cleopatra's cat the day before she died was an even number. Person B thinks that it was an odd number. We note the absence of any basis for determining which is true. Therefore, the (so-called) fact that the number of fleas on the cat was either odd or even is purely subjective".

My argument is actually stronger than yours, because - in asserting the lack of any objecive moral criteria you simply and flagranty beg the question against those who believe that there are such criteria, whereas there is no criteria (and no one thinks otherwise) for determining how many fleas were on a cat that died some two thousand years ago.

(Just reiterating the point about begging the question - has it not occurred to you that those who believe that morality is objective do not note that there are no objective critiera? That they in fact point to reasons that might tell in favour of one or the other of person A or person B?)

Nevertheless, my argument is probably not sound. The only mainstream philosopher I know of who accepts a version of it is Michael Dummett (perhaps also some of his followers, like Crispin Wright). Most people think that there can be an objective fact even though we have no means of ascertaining it.

As I have said, burden of proof really is not relevant to the metaphysics of morals. It's about 2500 years too late for it.
 

Hussar

Legend
Well granted, its not like the Eye of Vecna is on the random treasure table (though it might!) so its not like DM's hand it out haphazardly; they usually have a plot necessity to do so. A better example is putting stats for the Tarrasque in the Monster Manual; how many times are you seriously going to fight him?

And no problem; I've been skipping past the alignment/moral debate too.

How strenuously would you object to leaving him out?

But then, the Terrasque is actually a perfect example of what I want. Tons of flavour, totally setting light. It's not tied to any setting in any way. Who created it? Who knows? How does it relate to any other thing in the game? It doesn't. Yet you have a creature with lot of flavour that would be very exciting to add to a campaign and is easily dropped into any setting without having to worry about how it connects to anything else.

Would you expect to see a module with the Eye and Hand of Vecna that doesn't tie into Vecna, and quite probably Kaz as well?

What would you expect to see in a module with The Tarrasque?
 

Remove ads

AD6_gamerati_skyscraper

Remove ads

Recent & Upcoming Releases

Top