Dr. Awkward said:
Say what now? No it doesn't. You've been watching Temple of Doom too much. It implies that a sacrifice is being made, and that the sacrifice is a human life. I can sacrifice my life for a cause, or to save another, or I can be made sacrifice by someone else, with or without my consent.
Not at all. There is a very large difference between choosing to strive to complete a goal, and possibly dying in the process, and killing someone else to help you meet your goals.
Now, I'll grant you that language is a slippery fish, and the terms "human" and "sacrifice" both have more than one definition. I'll even grant you that by applying a moral judgment (or lack thereof) to one definition of a word, you can trick the unwary into thinking it applies to all definitions of the word.
Luckily for me, though, I started this thread. Since I asked the question, it seems reasonable that I should have the ability to define the question more clearly.
By human, it is meant not only members of the genus and species H. sapiens, but any sentient, self-aware person. Of course, in a D&D setting, this includes elves, dwarves, orcs, etc. Nor does the person have to be literally humanoid; dragons, outsiders, etc., could easily fit into the discussion parameters.
By sacrifice, it is meant as a noun,
1. The act of offering something to a deity in propitiation or homage, especially the ritual slaughter of an animal or a person.
2. A victim offered in this way.
or as a verb,
1. To offer as a sacrifice to a deity.
(Thank you, dictionary.com, for the quick cut-and-paste, as well as for having these as the first definitions of the terms!)
These are almost exlusively the definitions used in the term "human sacrifice" regardless of who is using the term. I repeat, this implies that the sacrifice is being performed by someone other than the victim. And again, I am pretty sure that you know this.
The thing it boils down to is consent. Sex is rape without consent, but with consent it's a wonderful thing.
From the SRD:
“Good” implies altruism, respect for life, and a concern for the dignity of sentient beings. Good characters make personal sacrifices to help others.
“Evil” implies hurting, oppressing, and killing others. Some evil creatures simply have no compassion for others and kill without qualms if doing so is convenient. Others actively pursue evil, killing for sport or out of duty to some evil deity or master.
Regardless of how you may feel about real-world ethics, it is explicit in D&D that good characters make
personal sacrifices (Dictionary.com definition 2: Forfeiture of something highly valued for the sake of one considered to have a greater value or claim) to help others; evil characters kill others
out of duty to some evil deity or master.
Given that good implies altruism, respect for life, and a concern for the dignity of sentient beings, it is fairly unlikely that the one requiring human sacrifice is good.
Given that "People who are neutral with respect to good and evil have compunctions against killing the innocent" it seems unlikely that the one requiring human sacrifices is neutral.
Given that evil implies hurting, oppressing, and killing others, it seems very likely that the one requiring human sacrifices is evil.
Or, to use your example, sex with consent is a neutral act. Wonderful thing or not, it isn't personal sacrifice. Sex without consent implies hurting and oppressing others, and falls well within the definition of evil in the SRD.
Killing someone, according to the SRD, is not a neutral act. It falls clearly within what is implied by the term "evil." If I am doing the killing, consent is not a factor.
If I help you kill yourself, at best I am performing a neutral act. The neutrality of the act relies upon either (1) the fact that you are going to die anyway (Spock's death at the end of Wrath of Khan; potentially some forms of assisted suicide) or (2) uncertainty that the outcome is your death (defense of Helm's Deep); either one coupled with (3) I cannot simply take your place (I cannot take on your incurable disease; it requires lots of people to defend the helpless), (4) you consent with reasonable knowledge of what you are consenting to, and (5)
I do not kill you myself.
In the related Is Slavery Evil thread, it was pointed out convincingly to me that in order for a good character to
be good in the D&D sense of the word, he or she
must be able to recognize evil for what it is. Social acceptance and moral relativism do not enter the picture.
Compare with the following from
http://www.law.yale.edu/outside/html/Publications/pub-katz.htm, which is dealing with real world law and ethics:
Jay Katz said:
The philosopher Hans Jonas, in a remarkable essay on human experimentation, comes close to equating human experimentation with the “primeval human sacrifices…that existed in some early societies [for] the solemn execution of a supreme, sacral necessity”; for he suggested that both involved “something sacrificial [in their] abrogation of personal inviolability and the ritualistic exposure to gratuitous risk of health and life, justified by a presumed greater social good.” Whatever the relationship between ancient religious practices of sacrifice as an offering to deity and scientific research practices of sacrifice as an offering to medical progress, the readiness with which human sacrifice for the sake of scientific progress has been embraced by the medical profession is remarkable. As one distinguished surgeon put it: “[Conducting] controlled studies may well sacrifice a generation of women but scientifically they have merit.”
René Girard, in his book, Violence and the Sacred, observes that “n many rituals the sacrificial act assumes two opposing aspects, appearing at times as a sacred obligation to be neglected at great peril, at other times as a sort of criminal activity entailing perils of equal gravity.” The conflict between medicine and law on the permissible limits of human experimentation, to which I shall return repeatedly, reflects these “opposing aspects.” When do such “sacred [scientific] obligations” become a “criminal activity”?
Sacrifice can be voluntary or involuntary. The distinction is crucial. But I shall argue that even voluntary sacrifice can be safeguarded only if investigators learn that seeking voluntary consent is their moral obligation, if they learn to desist from employing the concept of voluntary consent as a deceptive subterfuge to shift moral responsibility for participation in research from themselves to their patient-subjects.
Of course, consent has not always meant what one would normally think consent means.
Jay Katz said:
I believe that the concentration camp experiments, which transgressed the last vestiges of human decency, can be located at one end of a continuum, but I also believe that toward the opposite end, we must confront a question still relevant in today’s world: How much harm can be inflicted on human subjects of research for the sake of medical progress and national survival? Knowledge about hell can make investigators pause and reflect, as it did at times during the days of the Cold War, when a few American physician-scientists, while contemplating experiments much less egregious than those conducted by the Nazi physicians, asked: “Are we beginning to behave as they did?”
<snip>
The initial advances in knowledge that resulted from such scientific investigations, which promised to alleviate human suffering to an extent previously unknown, seemed to justify the means employed. The uncharted moral path led only once to Auschwitz; yet, on many other occasions down the road, human beings would pay a considerable price for the sake of medical progress.
The early fruits of medical research were spectacular. The bacterial etiology of many diseases was proved, resulting in cures never before the lot of mankind. Investigations of the use of X-rays to see the previously invisible revolutionized diagnostic techniques. Experiments with various anesthetic agents led to remarkable advances in surgery.
These experiments were largely conducted in public hospitals with the poor, with children, women, prostitutes, the elderly – that is, with the disadvantaged, the downtrodden.
Jay Katz said:
What is justice, what is injustice? A friend of mine once pointed out to me the repetition of the word justice in Deuteronomy: “Tzedek, tzedek tirdof” (Justice, justice, shalt thou pursue). Such a seemingly unnecessary repetition always invites commentary, and the one he heard was this: “justice can never be adequately pursued only as a goal or an idea; it is also reflected in the means employed.”
I personally believe that Mr. Katz's conclusion here is correct, in the real world as well as in D&D. Either way, the SRD seems to define alignment not only by what your goals are, but also -- and quite emphatically so -- by what you are willing to do to achieve them.
RC