Dr. Awkward said:
However, I do maintain that the act itself has no moral content, and that the morality of an event has its ground entirely in the actors involved. <snip> So the intention of both actors must be taken into account.
And this is where the moral relativists usually lose me. Moral relativism argues that intentions define the action. I disagree. Actions have value irrespective of the intentions that spawned them. Good intentions can lead to evil actions and evil intentions can lead to good actions.
Since ethics exists only when there are multiple actors involved in a situation, the agency of each actor must be considered. However, it is clear that when all actors are in agreement, there is no moral ambiguity. The question of whether something is a good or evil act only arises when the actors disagree on the best way to proceed.
I still just don't buy that. Two good intentioned people can agree to commit an evil act together. Being in agreement doesn't necessarily mean that someone isn't being harmed.
You're going to have to make a case for why such an act is evil. If you are trying to claim that killing another is always evil, in any situation, then you've got some work to do to back up that claim.
I don't make that claim. There are lots of situations where killing someone is definitely a good act. However, killing an innocent person (one for whom death isn't a consequence of their own informed actions) is, IMO, always an evil act - even if its necessary to perform some greater good and all parties agree that the act should be performed.
Consider, for example, Sue Rodriguez, a Canadian woman who was suffering from a terminal illness <snip> once she was no longer able to take her own life, she desired to die. It follows that in order for her desire to avoid either a torturous, slow death, or an early end that would deprive her of quality of life (in this case spending time with her loved ones before she goes) someone would have to kill her.
Ending someone's suffering is a good act (AFAIC). Killing an innocent person is evil. In this case, to do good, someone also had to commit evil. Helping Ms. Rodriguez to die, if that was her choice required an otherwise good person to commit a merciful, kind, compassionate act of evil. It does not make them an evil person, but the facts surrounding their act cannot change the status of their action. Ask yourself this, if someone burst into the room at the last minute and declared there was a way to end Ms. Rodriguez' suffering without killing her or hurting anyone else, would ANYONE want the euthanasia to proceed? For every good person, I'm pretty sure the answer would be no. Hopefully the same thing would go for poorl old Steve

. So, ask yourself WHY we would be happy to pursue another alternative, if one presented itself. Is it because we're choosing between two good acts, or is it because we are now able to choose between a good action that requires us to commit a concurrent evil action and a good action that
doesn't require a corresponding evil action? I think it's the latter.
Now, if you want to claim otherwise, you have to provide some reason why I should believe that it's an evil act. Simply saying "all killing is evil" doesn't cut it, because I happen to disagree that this is the case, and will need to be convinced by a reasoned argument. If no such argument exists, that means that the position is entirely parochial, and need not be considered.
I think you're mistaking me for a moral absolutist.
I'm not claiming that good and evil are concrete values that can be measured or proven. I'm arguing for a position that accepts the basic thesis that there are no moral absolutes, but doesn't accept the thesis that moral values only depend upon the intentions of the actors. You're taking two separate acts 1) ending someone's suffering, and 2) ending someone's life and mushing them together, claiming that the values attached to one cancel out the values attached to another (i.e. if #1 is a +50 on the "good" scale and #2 is -25 on the "evil" scale, then the overall act is a +25 "good"). You're doing so because both actions in your specific example are inextricably linked through circumstance. However, constructing a specific example in which the two actions cannot take place separately doesn't necessarily mean we can't place value judgements on them separately, especially if we can construct situations where they are separate and the value judgements become clear. Because humans are thinking, reasoning creatures we are able to look at a situation where two actions with separate value judgements are inextricably linked and make a determination (as in this case) whether the good of a good action can justify the evil of an evil action. However,
justify does not equate to
eliminate. The good that comes of an evil action may give ample reason for its commission, but it doesn't change the inherent value attached to the action, it only changes the value attached to the big picture outcome.
You have allowed that it wouldn't be wrong if Steve was enthusiastic about dying to save people, but not if he was only grudgingly accepting of the responsibility.
Actually, that's not really what I said. It doesn't matter whether Steve is grudging or enthusiastic. What matters is, if Steve was presented with the option of being a hero and saving the world that DIDN'T involve him dying (and didn't involve anything else that might be considered evil or off-putting) would he still choose to die? For example, if - while Steve is on the altar - a scientist discovered that Steve (and only Steve) could instead save the earth by reciting the words
Klatu Verata Nikto, would Steve choose NOT to die and say the words or would he still choose to die? If Steve WANTS to die; if dying is not only the means to an end but an end desired by Steve in and of itself, then I can accept the idea that helping Steve to die would not be an evil act. But if given the option to achieve all his other ends without dying and without suffering any other undesirable consequences, Steve would choose to live, then killing Steve (even with his full consent) would be an evil act.
But I don't believe that most paladins would sacrifice an unwilling or willing innocent in order to save everyone else. I figure the paladin would put himself on the altar instead, which is a good act. Self-sacrifice to help others is always good.
Again, you're mushing together two separate acts with separate value attachments. Helping others is good, killing yourself is bad (even if it's sometimes justifiable or necessary). Sometimes the help you bring to others by doing a bad thing makes the bad thing desirable or necessary.
Only if the person not acting has sworn to act. We cannot expect or enforce "good samaritanism". This is unreasonable. We might find those who are unwilling to make sacrifices to be lacking in strength of character, but we would not characterize them as evil, just cowardly.
I think that the act of being a Paladin
definitely implies a resolution to act in certain circumstances. I suppose a Paladin's code of conduct could contain only negative statements (i.e. Thou shalt not.....), but then you're basically end up with a class of Paladins who were more "do nothings" than "do gooders". The archetype of the Paladin implies that Paladins are not only compelled to avoid certain behaviors but to engage in certain, inherently "good", behaviors. So, I would argue that being a Paladin inherently requires "good samaritanism" and avoiding cowardice. YMMV.